|
[CLICK
ON THE TITLE ABOVE TO PURCHASE THE BOOK FROM TAN.]
God, the Ultimate Foundation of Duty
We
have been considering the proof for the existence of the sovereign good
based on our natural desire for happiness. It may be summed up, we
said, in this way: A
natural desire,
one that has its foundation not in the imagination or the vagaries of
reason but in our very nature, which we have in common with all men, cannot
possibly be ineffective, chimerical,
deceptive; this means that it cannot be for a good that is either
unreal or unattainable.
Now
every man has a natural desire for happiness, and true happiness is
not to be found in any finite or limited good, for our intellect, with
its conception of universal, unlimited good, naturally constrains us
to desire it.
There
must, then, be an
unlimited good,
pure and simple, without any admixture of non-good or imperfection;
without it the universal range of our will would be a psychological
absurdity and without any meaning whatever.
If
the herbivora find the grass they need and the carnivora the prey
necessary for their sustenance, then the natural desire in man cannot
be to no purpose. The natural desire for true happiness must be
possible of attainment and, since it is to be found only in the
knowledge and love of the sovereign good, and this is God, then God
must exist.
There
is another proof for God's existence, the starting-
point
of which is not in our desire for happiness but in moral
obligation or the direction of our will to moral. good. This proof
leads up to the sovereign good, not considered as simply the supreme
desirable but as possessing the right to be loved, as having a claim on
our love, and as the foundation of duty.
1)
The ordering of our will to moral good
This
proof has its starting-point in human conscience. All men,
including even those who doubt the existence of God, realize, at least
vaguely, that one must do
good and avoid evil.
To recognize this truth it is enough to have a notion of "good" and to
distinguish, as common sense does, between (1) sensible or purely
delectable goods, (2) good that is useful in view of some end, and (3)
honorable or moral good (bonum
honestum),
which is good in itself independently of the enjoyment or utility it
may afford. The animal finds its complete satisfaction in delectable
good of the senses; by instinct it makes use of sensible good that it
fInds to be useful, but without perceiving that the
raison d'être
of the useful lies in the end for which it is employed. The swallow
picks up a piece of straw with which to make its nest without knowing
that the straw is of use in building it. Man alone, through his reason,
recognizes that the utility or raison
d' être of the means
lies
in the end they subserve.
Again,
he alone recognizes and can love the honorable
good;
he alone can understand this moral truth: that one must do good and
avoid evil. The imagination of the brute may be trained and continually
perfected in its own order, but never will it succeed in grasping this
truth.
But,
on the other hand, every man, however uncultured he may be, will
grasp this truth as soon as he comes to the age of reason. Everyone who
has come to the full use of reason will recognize this threefold
distinction in the good, even though he may not always be able to put
it into words. It is obvious to anyone that a tasty fruit is a
delectable good of the sensible order, a physical good having nothing
to do with moral good, since the use it is put to may be either morally
good or morally bad: the delectable is not therefore in itself moral.
Again,
all are aware that a bitter medicine is not a delectable
good,
but one that is useful in view of some end, as a possible means of
recovering their health. In this way money is useful and, from the
moral point of view, the use it is put to may be either good or bad.
Here is one of the most elementary principles of common sense.
Lastly,
everyone who has come to the age of reason sees that transcending the
delectable and the useful there is the honorable
good,
the rational or moral good, which is good in itself independently of
any pleasure or advantage or convenience resulting from it.
In
this sense virtue
is a good,
such as patience, courage, justice. That justice is a spiritual good
and not a sensible one is obvious to everybody. Though it may bring joy
to the person practicing it, it is good regardless of this enjoyment;
it is good because it is reasonable or in conformity with right reason.
We are fully aware that justice must be practiced for its own sake and
not merely for the advantage to be gained, let us say, in avoiding the
evil consequences of injustice. Thus, even though it should mean
certain death to us, we are bound to do justice and avoid injustice,
especially where the injustice is grave.
This
is a perfection belonging to man as man, to man as a rational being,
and not as an animal.
To
know truth, to love it above all things, to act in all things in
accordance with right reason, is likewise good in itself apart from the
pleasure we may find in it or the advantages to be gained thereby.
Furthermore,
this honorable or rational good is presented to us as the
necessary end of our activity and hence as of obligation. Everyone is
aware that a rational being must behave in conformity with right
reason, even as reason itself is in conformity with the absolute
principles of being or reality: "That which is, is, and cannot at the
same time be and not be." The honest man who is beaten unmercifully by
some scamp proves to him the superiority of the intelligible world over
that of sense when he exclaims: "You may be the stronger, but that does
not prove that you are right." Justice is justice.
"Do
your duty, come what may," "one must do good and avoid evil." In
these or equivalent formulas the idea of duty finds expression among
all peoples. Pleasure and self-interest must be subordinated to duty,
the delectable and the useful to the moral. Here we have an eternal
truth, which has always been true and will ever be so.
What
is the proximate basis of duty or moral obligation?
As St. Thomas (Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 2) says, this basis is the principle
of finality, evident to our intellect, according to which every being
acts in view of some end and must tend to that end which is
proportionate to it. Whence it follows that in rational beings the will
must tend to the honorable or rational good, to which it has been
ordered. The faculty to will and act rationally is for the rational act
as the eye is for seeing, the ear for hearing, the foot for walking,
the wings of the bird for flying, the cognitive faculty for knowing. A
potency is for its correlative act; if it fails to tend to that act it
ceases to have a raison
d'être. It is not
merely better for the faculty to tend to its act, it is its intrinsic
primordial law.
Since
over and above the sensible, the delectable, and the useful good,
the will from its very nature is capable of desiring the honorable or
rational good (and this is equivalent to saying that it is essentially
ordered to that good), it cannot refuse to desire that good without
ceasing to have a raison
d'être.
The will is for the purpose of loving and desiring rational good; this
good must therefore be realized by it --- by man, that is, who is
capable
of realizing this good and who exists for such purpose. This is the
proximate basis of moral obligation. But is there not also a far nobler
and ultimate basis?
The
voice
of conscience is
peculiarly insistent at times in commanding or forbidding the
performance of certain acts --- in forbidding perjury or treason, for
instance --- or again in rebuking and condemning when a grave offense
has
been committed. Is not the murderer tormented by his conscience after
his crime, even when the deed is perpetrated in complete secrecy? The
crime is unknown to men, yet conscience never ceases to upbraid him
even though he chooses to doubt God's existence.
Where
does this voice of conscience come from? Is it simply the result
of a logical process? Does it come simply from our own reason? No, for
it makes itself heard in each and every human being; it dominates them
all.
Is
it the result of human legislation? No, for it is above human
legislation, above the legislation of anyone nation, of every nation
and of the League of Nations. It is this voice which tells us that an
unjust law is not binding in conscience; those who enact unjust laws
are themselves rebuked in the secrecy of their hearts by the persistent
voice of right reason.
2)
The ordering of our will to moral good presupposes a Divine intelligent
designer
Whence,
then, comes this voice of conscience, so insistent at times? We
take for granted that a means cannot be ordered to an end except by an
intelligent designer, who alone can recognize in the end to be attained
the raison d'être of
the means, and therefore can alone determine the means to the end. We
take for granted also, as was seen above (chap. 2), that the order in
the physical universe presupposes a Divine intelligent designer. Then
with much greater reason must such an intellect be presupposed in the
ordering of our will to moral good. There is no passive direction
without a corresponding active direction, which in this case must be
from the very Author of our nature.
Again,
if from the eternal speculative truths (such as, that the same
thing cannot at the same time be and not be), we pass by a necessary
transition to the existence of a supreme Truth, the fountain of all
other truths, why should we not ascend from the first principle of the
moral law (it is necessary to do good and avoid evil) up to the eternal
law?
Here
we begin with the practical instead of the speculative principles;
the obligatory character of the good merely gives a new aspect to the
proof, and this characteristic, evident already in the proximate
basis of moral
obligation, leads us on to seek its ultimate
basis.
If
honorable good, to which our rational nature is ordered, must be desired
apart from the satisfaction or advantages we derive from it; if that
being which is capable of desiring it must do so under
pain of ceasing to have a raison d'être;
if our conscience loudly proclaims this duty and thereafter approves or
condemns without our being able to stifle remorse of conscience; if, in
a word, the right to be loved and practiced inherent in the good
dominates the whole of our moral activity and that of every society,
actual or possible, as the principle of con tradition dominates all
reality, actual or possible: then of necessity there must exist from
all eternity some basis on which these absolute rights inherent in the
good are founded.
These
claims inherent in justice dominate our individual, family,
social, and political lives, and dominate the international life of
nations, past, present, and to come. These necessary and predominating
rights cannot have their raison
d'être
in the contingent, transient realities which they dominate, nor even in
those manifold and subordinate goods or duties which are imposed upon
us as rational beings. Transcending as they do everything that is not
the Good itself, the rights of justice can have none but that Good as
their foundation, their ultimate reason.
If,
then, the proximate
basis of moral obligation
lies in the essential order of things, or, to be more precise, in the
rational good to which our nature and activity are essentially ordered,
its ultimate
basis is to be
found in the sovereign good, our objective last end. This moral
obligation could only have been established by a law of the same order
as the sovereign good --- by the Divine wisdom, whose eternal law
orders
and directs all creatures to their end. Agent and end are in
corresponding orders. The passive direction on the part of our will to
the good presupposes an active direction on the part of Him who created
it for the good. In other words, in rational beings the will must tend
to the honorable or rational good, since this is the purpose for which
it was created by a higher efficient cause, who Himself had in view the
realization of this good.
This
is why, according to common sense or natural reason, duty
is in the last resort founded on the being, intelligence, and will of
God,
Who has created us to know, love, and serve Him and thereby obtain
eternal bliss.
And
so, common sense has respect for duty, while at the same time it
regards as legitimate our search after happiness. It rejects
utilitarian morality on the one hand, and on the other Kantian
morality, which consists in pure duty to the exclusion of all objective
good. To common sense this latter is like an arid waste where the sun
never shines.
Against
this demonstration of God's existence, the objection is
sometimes advanced that it is a begging of the question, that it
involves a vicious circle. Strictly speaking, there is no moral
obligation, So it is said, without a supreme law-giver, and it is
impossible to regard ourselves as subject to a categorical moral
obligation unless this supreme lawgiver is first recognized. Hence the
proof put forward presupposes what it seeks to prove; at the most it
brings out more explicitly what is presumed to be already implicitly
admitted.
To
this we may reply, and rightly so, that it is sufficient first of
all to show the passive direction of our will to moral good and then go
on to prove the further truth that, since there can be no passive
direction without an active direction, there must exist a first cause
who has so given this tendency to the will. Thus we have seen that the
order in the world presupposes a supreme intelligent designer, and that
the eternal truths governing all contingent reality and every finite
intelligence themselves require an eternal foundation.
Moreover,
this passive direction of our will to moral good is not the
only starting-point from which we may argue. We may also begin with
moral obligation as evidenced in its effects, in the remorse felt by
the murderer, for instance. Whence comes this terrible voice of remorse
of conscience which the criminal never succeeds in silencing in the
depths of his soul?
Right
reason within us commands us to do good, that rational good to
which our rational nature is directed. Nevertheless it does not command
as a first and eternal cause; for in each of us reason first of all
begins to command, then it slumbers, and is awakened again; it has many
imperfections, many limitations. It is not the principle of all order,
but is itself ordered. We must therefore ascend higher to that divine
wisdom by which everything is directed to the supreme good.
There
alone do we find the ultimate
basis of moral obligation or duty. There is no
vicious circle; from the feeling of remorse or from its contrary, peace
of mind, we ascend to conscience.
In the approval or disapproval of conscience lies the explanation of
these feelings. We then look for the source of this voice of
conscience. The ultimate source is not in our imperfect reason, for
reason in its commanding had a beginning. It commands only as secondary
cause, presupposing a first cause that is eternal, simple, and
perfect wisdom itself, by which everything is directed to the good.
The
sovereign good is now no longer presented simply as the supreme
desirable, wherein alone we may find true happiness, if we love it
above all things; it is further presented as the sovereign good which
must be loved above all things, which demands our love and is the
foundation of duty.
From
all this it is plain that, if the primary duty toward God the last
end of man is denied, then every other duty is deprived of its ultimate
foundation. If we deny that we are morally bound to love before all
else the good as such and God the sovereign good, what proof have we
that we are bound to love that far less compelling good, the general
welfare of humanity, which is the main object of the League of Nations?
What proof have we that we are bound to love our country and family
more than our life; or that we are bound to go on living and avoid
suicide, even in the most overwhelming afflictions? If the sovereign
good has not an inalienable right to be loved above all things, then a
fortiori inferior
goods have no such right. If we are not morally bound
by a last end, then no end or means whatever is morally binding. If the
foundation for moral obligation is not in a supreme lawgiver, then
every human law is deprived of its ultimate foundation.
Such
is the proof for the existence of God as supreme lawgiver and
the sovereign good, who is the foundation of duty. Such is the eminent
origin of the imperious voice of conscience, that voice which torments
the criminal after his crime and gives to the conscientious who have
done their utmost, that peace which comes from duty accomplished.
The
moral sanction
In
conclusion we shall say a few words about another proof for the
existence of God, a proof closely related to the preceding: that based
on moral sanction.
The
consideration of heroic
acts unrequited here on
earth and of crimes
that go unpunished shows us the
necessity of a sovereign judge, a rewarder and vindicator.
The existence
of this sovereign judge and of an eternal sanction may be
proved from the insufficiency of all other sanctions. Kant himself
chose to attach some importance to this argument, but in itself it is
far more convincing than he made it out to be. It may be summed up in
this way:
By
perseverance in virtue the just man merits happiness since he has
persevered in doing good. Now the harmony prevailing between virtue and
happiness, in another and better life, is accomplished by God alone.
Therefore God and that other life exist.
The more
exalted a man's moral life is, the firmer and livelier is his
conviction resulting from this proof. In reality it presupposes the
preceding proof and is a confirmation of it. If, in fact, the voice of
conscience comes from the supreme lawgiver, then He must also be the
sovereign judge Who rewards
and vindicates.
Because He is intelligent and good, He owes it to Himself to give to
every being what is necessary for it to attain the end for which He has
destined it, and hence to give to the just that knowledge of truth and
that beatitude which they deserve. (Cf. St. Thomas, Ia, q. 21, a. 1.)
Furthermore, since the supreme lawgiver must of necessity love the good
above all things, He owes it to Himself also to compel respect for its
absolute rights and repress their violation (Ia IIae, q. 87, a. 1, 3).
In
other words, if there is order in the physical world and if that
order demands an intelligent designer, much more must there be order
in the moral world, which is on
an infinitely higher plane.
Herein
is the answer to the complaints of the just who are persecuted
and unjustly condemned by men. How often in this world do the wicked
and indifferent triumph, while upright and high-minded souls, like Joan
of Arc, are condemned? Barabbas was even preferred to Jesus; Barabbas
was set free and Jesus was crucified. Injustice cannot have the last
word, especially when it is so flagrant as this. There is a higher
justice; its voice makes itself heard in our conscience and it will one
day restore all things to the true order. Then will be clearly made
manifest the two aspects of the Sovereign Good: His right to be loved
above all things, which is the principle of justice, and His being
essentially self-diffusive, which is the principle of mercy.
These
moral proofs for the existence of God are of a nature to convince
any mind that does not try to stifle the interior voice of conscience.
Such a mind will have little difficulty in discovering the deeper
source of this voice directing us to the good, because it comes from
Him Who is the good itself.
www.catholictradition.org/Christ/providence2-5.htm
|